Marx, Proudhon, and Alternatives to Capital

By Seth Weiss.

Marx’s critical dialogue with the work of the French anarchist thinker Pierre Joseph Proudhon spanned several decades-from his youth haunting the cafes of Paris, where he had occasion to meet Proudhon and discuss German philosophy, through the writing of the GrundrisseCapital, and theCritique of the Gotha Program. While largely ignored in the present, Marx’s critique of Proudhon remains of real import for all of us struggling to break the hold of capital over our lives and our world.
Three aspects of Marx’s critique will be explored here: (I) the limits of reforms in the sphere of circulation; (II) economic laws and the possibilities which politics and consciousness offer for their transcendence; and (III) Marx’s still largely uncharted concept of “directly social labor.”

‘Fair Trade’

In his 1846 Philosophy of Poverty, Proudhon locates a contradiction between use-value and exchange-value-a contradiction which he holds as the basis of poverty, inequality, and economic crises. With what he terms “constituted value” or “synthetic value,” Proudhon, drawing on the value theory of classical political economy, endeavors a resolution of the contradiction. “Synthetic value,” Proudhon maintains, is the ground for abolishing unequal exchange. (1) What Proudhon is proposing, in practical terms is that one commodity which requires, for instance, four hours to produce will exchange with any other commodity that requires four hours to produce. For Proudhon this would be a situation of equality: equal contributions to society receiving equal rewards from society.

A year later, in his 1847 Poverty of Philosophy, the only book that he wrote in French, Marx tears this formulation to pieces. Proudhon, Marx argues, “give[s] as a ‘revolutionary theory of the future’ what Ricardo expounded scientifically as the theory of present-day society, of bourgeois society, and…thus take[s] for the solution of the antinomy between utility and exchange value what Ricardo and his school presented long before him as the scientific formula of one single side of this antinomy, that of exchange value.” Moreover, says Marx, “relative value [or exchange-value], measured by labor time, is inevitably the formula of the present enslavement of the worker, instead of being, as M. Proudhon would have it, the ‘revolutionary theory’ of the emancipation of the proletariat.”

Marx understood the law of value rather differently than Proudhon: not in terms of “equality” but in terms of “inequality.” What appears as an equality is just that-an appearance-because it is not individual, concrete labor that has a tendency to exchange in equal ratios, but only socially average, abstract labor. In Capital, Marx shows that the value of a commodity is determined by the amount of “socially necessary labor-time” required for its reproduction-any labor-time beyond that which is socially necessary is simply wasted (i.e., labor-time during which no value is created). (2)

The fact that our labor doesn’t count equally is not because of unequal exchange, but because our labor is not counted equally in the first place-in the process of production. The labor of some workers counts more than the labor of other workers in production. One worker, for instance, may be stronger or faster than another worker; one worker may be working with more modern technology than another. Only socially necessary labor, labor which measures up to the social average, is registered in our society.

Marx maintains that relations of exchange are rooted in the relations of production. Unequal exchange, or rather what appears as unequal exchange, ultimately can’t be overcome without uprooting present production relations and transcending value production.

Much of the Left today-including both anarchists and Marxists-continues to locate the roots of poverty, inequality and economic crises in the realm of exchange and to prescribe remedies that focus on exchange. This is particularly pronounced in the anti-globalization movement. Think about campaigns for “Fair Trade” (rather than “Free Trade”) and the work of organizations like Global Exchange and Trade Craft. Consider also the recent Life After Capitalism conference at the CUNY Graduate Center, which featured panels promoting gift-exchange and barter as alternatives to capitalism. The panel on the latter was called “The Barter System in Argentina: is it Possible in our Town?”

Marx’s critique of Proudhon demands that we consider whether efforts at abolishing markets or changing property relations can offer ground for real social transformation. In this, it also demands that we rethink the experience of the Soviet Union, China, Cuba and the other so-called “socialist” countries. The new global justice movements have largely rejected this experience as a model-they have rejected the vanguard party, the seizure of state power, the five-year plan. This is plainly sensible-but it is a partial critique: it is not sufficient to counterpose new decentralized and anti-authoritarian movements to the old vanguardist movements. Like with Proudhon’s work, there is a failure to look closely at the mode of production itself. To be sure, some property relations were changed and some wealth was redistributed in the so-called “socialist” countries, but value production was simply not overcome and labor remained alienated.

A second feature of Marx’s critique of Proudhon that deserves attention is his treatment of economic laws and their transcendence.

Can Politics Break the Law of Value?

Proudhon argues that the contradiction he finds between “use-value” and “exchange-value” is also a contradiction between “supply” and “demand.” Proudhon’s concerns are practical in nature. The 1840s, known as the “hungry forties,” witnessed severe economic crisis across the continent, culminating in the revolutions of 1848. In a crisis demand drops off-things can’t be sold and prices fall. Proudhon says that the contradiction between supply and demand can be overcome if commodities are made to exchange directly in proportion to the amount of labor required for their production. Set prices equal to values, so that supply and demand find equilibrium, and voila: commodities will always be exchangeable and at a fair price.

Marx maintains, in the Poverty of Philosophy, that Proudhon “inverts the order of things.” For it is when supply and demand come into balance that prices equal values. (3) Marx jokes that while everyone else ventures outside for a walk when the weather is good, Proudhon would have us leave the house to insure good weather!

In the course of his discussion of these issues in the Poverty of Philosophy, Marx draws an important distinction between the role of a “legislator” and that of an “economist.” As a legislator, Marx tells us, Proudhon is free to decree the abolition of the law of supply and demand. However, says Marx, “[i]f…he [Proudhon] insists on justifying his theory, not as a legislator, but as an economist [my emphasis], he will have to prove that the time needed to create a commodity indicates exactly the degree of its utility and marks its proportional relation to the demand…” A legislator-and for Marx’s legislator we could easily substitute a central committee, a workers’ council or a worker-run co-op-may be able to decree that one hour of labor is equal to another. However, what will happen when demand for a product-as with typewriters in the advent of the personal computer-drops off? The labor that went into the production of the typewriters will no longer count -they simply won’t sell, their price will fall, workers will lose their jobs.

While Proudhon was content to remain a captive of the commodity-form, there are many of us today who want to transcend commodity production and transcend capital. Can we legislate the abolition of commodity production? Can politics break the law of value?

Too often we seem to be thinking like Marx’s “legislator.” Much of the Left today-from Stalinists to social democrats to anarchists-seems to believe that politics are in command. Too often, regardless of whether one’s program demands seizing state power or smashing state power, the problematic remains limited to matters of political power, consciousness, and organizational form.

Proudhon’s interest in the equilibration of supply and demand led him to advocate the abolition of money. In the course of his critique of this aspect of Proudhon’s thought, Marx elaborates a crucially important notion-namely that of “directly social labor”-which is still not well understood.

Directly Social Labor

Marx develops the concept of “directly social labor” or “immediately social labor” in critical dialogue with the work of Proudhon, the Ricardian socialists and later with the followers of Ferdinand Lassalle. In endeavoring an equalitarian application of Ricardo’s theory, Proudhon and left Ricardian thinkers like John Gray, advocated what we would today call monetary reform: they sought to replace money with “time chits” or “labor money.” These “time chits” were designed to directly reflect labor time. In other words, in exchange for a commodity that took, say, 12 hours to produce, the producer would receive a certificate from a bank entitling her to any other commodity that took 12 hours to produce. Proudhon and Gray wanted every commodity to be directly social, directly exchangeable, with every other commodity in the same way that money is directly social. Proudhon and the other “time-chitters,” as Marx calls them in the Grundrisse, thought the mediation of money stood in the way. (4)

Marx, however, cautions us not to get caught up in money’s dazzle and sheen. Money, Marx argues in Volume I of Capital, crystallizes out of a contradiction within the commodity itself: a contradiction in the commodity between “use-value” on the one hand and “value” on the other hand; a contradiction between “concrete labor” (labor which produces use-values) and “abstract labor” (labor which produces value); and a contradiction between “private labor” (the labor of the individual) and “directly social labor” (the labor that society counts). One can’t then abolish money without abolishing the commodity-form.

Proudhon’s “pious wish” to abolish money without abolishing commodity production, Marx says inCapital, is rooted in “the illusion…that all commodities can simultaneously be imprinted with the stamp of direct exchangeability, in the same way that it might be imagined that all Catholics can be popes.” In other words, as long as there are commodities, one commodity will necessarily take the form of Pope ruling over all the other commodities.

In the 1875 Critique of the Gotha Program, Marx again returns to the issue of “directly social labor.” Marx’s characterization here of a higher phase of communism in which society will inscribe upon its banners “from each according to her ability, to each according to her needs” is well known. His characterization of the lower phase of communism remains poorly understood. In this lower phase, Marx says:

[T]he individual producer receives back from society…exactly what he gives to it…He receives a certificate from society that he has furnished such-and-such an amount of labor…and with this certificate he draws from the social stock of means of consumption as much as the same amount of labor costs. The same amount of labor which he has given to society in one form, he receives back in another.

This sounds very much like the proposals of Proudhon and other “time-chitters” that were the subject of decades of invective from Marx. There is, however, a real difference between what Marx is suggesting and the formulations of Proudhon-if we can get at this difference, we will have understood not only Marx’s critique of Proudhon but also have discovered one of the real clues that Marx has left us for figuring out how to transcend capital.

The difference is that, here, labor is “directly” or “immediately” social. Unlike in the formulations of Proudhon and unlike in our own commodity-producing society, where the exchange of equivalents exists only in the average, here there would actually be an exchange of equivalents in the individual case. “[N]ow,” as Marx notes, “in contrast to capitalist society, individual labor no longer exists in an indirect fashion but directly as a component part of total labor.” So here, right from the beginning, Marx is telling us that the law of value will not hold. The labor, Marx says, employed in the production of products will no longer take the form of a material quality possessed by them; the products of our own hands will no longer have control over us.

While Proudhon is not well remembered today, the kinds of ideas that he advanced have become conventional wisdom on the Left, particularly in the new global justice movements. A return to Marx’s critique of Proudhon offers a salutary antidote to such conventional wisdom and, perhaps, a path forward for all of us searching for real alternatives to capital.

Footnotes:

1. Ricardo’s Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, which posits labor as the source of value and labor-time as its measure, had been translated into French more than a decade before Proudhon’s Philosophy of Poverty was first published.

2. “Socially necessary labour-time is the labour-time required to produce any use-value under the conditions of production normal for a given society and with the average degree of skill and intensity of labour prevalent in that society” (Capital, p. 129, Penguin edition). In the Philosophy of Poverty, Marx posits the labor-time required by the most productive workers (rather than “socially necessary labor-time”) as determining the magnitude of value.

3. Strictly speaking, as Marx shows elsewhere, when supply equals demand, prices in the market equal prices of production, not values.

4. Ideas of this kind still remain with us today -e.g., alternative currency schemes like “Ithaca Dollars,” the “LETSystem” and “Burlington Bread” (which is denominated in “slices”).

(This essay originally published in News and Letters, July-August 2005)


7 Comments on “Marx, Proudhon, and alternatives to capital”

  1. 1Nickglais said at 4:23 pm on May 5th, 2009:P. J Proudon’s The Philosophy of Misery, or the System of Economical Contradictions (1846)strong contains a long section on competition which attempts to show that because the aims of communism are hostile to competition, communism is utopian, that it is merely a dream. (We quote from the English Edition of 1888″ competition is as essential to labour as division, since it is division itself returning in another form, or rather raised to its second power.. competition is in a word is liberty in division and in all the divided parts (Page 223) Competition is a principle of social economy, a decree of destiny, a necessity of the human soul.. (p229) ” Man rouses from his idelness only when want fills him from anxiety; and the surest way to extinguish his genius .. is to take away from him all hope of profit and of social distiction which results from it (page 234) competition on its useful side should be universal and carried to its maximum of intensity. (page 251).”Can competition in labour be abolished ? It would be as well worth while to ask if personality, liberty, indivudual responsibility can be supressed (page 258) there can be no question of destroying competition, as impossible as to destroy liberty: the problem is to find its equilibrium,
    I would willing say its police (page 261)

    ” They ( the communists) say : emulation is not competition. But emulation is nothing but competition itself. There is no emulation without an object: just as there is no passional initiative without an object, and as the object of every passion is analagous to the passion itself, woman to the lover, gold to the miser, crown to the poet – so the object of industrial emulation is profit. Why substitute for the immediate object of emulation, which is personal welfare, that far away and almost metaphysical motive called general welfare, especially when the latter is nothing without the former and can result only in the former.

    “My sole reply to him ( the communist) shall be : In denying competition you abandon the thesis: henceforth you have no place in the discussion.

    The question is the solution of the problem of competition – that is the reconciliation of egoism with socal necessities: spare your moralities (page 225-6)

    But if they the ( the communists) now fall back upon the hypothesis of transformation of our nature, unprecedented in history.. its is nothing more than a dream… a contradiction given to the most certain economic sciences; and my only reply is to exclude it from the discussion (page 228)

    Man may love his fellow well enough to die for him; he does not love him well enough to work for him”

    Because of its hostility to competition ” Communism is the very denial of society in its foundation” and the communists are “incessantly confounding matters of reason with those of sentiment” (page 283)

    The above may have been written by the great annd fearless revisionist Marxist Ota Sik himself.

    But let us see how the unrepentent Communist Karl Marx replied to the Philosophy of Misery in the Misery of Philosophy (1848) and we will see the aptness of his reply to the present day philosophers of misery, the solemn, long faced, mournful and miserable ideologists of market socialism.

    “M Proudhon begins by defending the eternal necessity of competition against those who wish to replace it with emulation. Competition is emulation with a view to profit. Is industrial emulation necessarily emulation with a view to profit, that is competition ? M Proudhon proves it by affirming it. ( page 163)

    “If the immediate object of a lover is a woman, the immediate object of industrial emulation is the product and not the profit.”

    “Competition is not industrial emultion it is commercial emulation.In our time industrial emulation exists only with a view to commerce. There are even phases in the life of modern nations when everybody is seized with a sort of craze for making profit without producing. This speculation craze which recurrs periodically, lays bare the true character of competition, which seeks to escape the need for industrial emulation (page 165).

    The distinction between competition and emulation is of crucial importance. “Competition is not industrial emulation, It is commercial emulation” ” The immediate object of industrial emulation is the product and not the profit”.

    This distinction between competition and emulation is blurred by all varities of opportunism. It is easy to see why revisionists should wish to blurr it so as to make competition appear as a category of production as such instead of being mere a category of the commercial system.

    On the other hand there are some so called anti revisionists who represent Stakhanovism, for example as a system of competition instead of industrial emulation. Thus revisionism and petty bourgeois Utopianism blur this vital distinction.

    Bu it is clear that industrial emulation, in which the object is the product, is entirely different from , and of infinitely more significance in the development of the productive forces than, competition, whose object is profit made on the sale of the product.

    As for Proudhon’s good and bad sides of competition which recurrs in modern revisionism, and the notion that what is required is to abolish the bad side of competition, while maintaing and developing its good side;

    ” They all want competition without the lethal effects of competition. They all want the impossible, namely the conditions of bourgeois existence without the necessary consequences of those conditions (page 213)

    The “bad side” is an integral part of the competitive relationship.Thee is no possibility of retaining the competitive realtionship while eliminating is “bad side”.

    Proudhon saw it as a necessity of thre human soul that only competitive struggle for profit roused man from ihe innate tendency to idelness and stagnation.

    This notion also recurs as a fundamental part of political economy of modern revisionism. The effect of the bourgeois system is represented as the cause of the bourgeois ( or market socialist ) system in human nature.

    Marx commented;

    ” the bourgeois man is to them the only possible basis of every society; they cannot imagine a society where men have ceased to be bourgoeis (213).

    “M. Proudhon does not know that all history is nothing but a continuous transformation of human nature” (page 165)

  2. 2Andrew Kliman said at 1:13 am on May 6th, 2009:Hi Nick,On your comment that “Proudhon saw it as a necessity of the human soul that only competitive struggle for profit roused man from the innate tendency to idleness and stagnation,” and Marx’s response.The following year, in the _Communist Manifesto_, there’s also this response (which I really get a kick out of):

    “It has been objected that upon the abolition of private property, all work will cease, and universal laziness will overtake us.

    “According to this, bourgeois society ought long ago to have gone to the dogs through sheer idleness; for those of its members who work, acquire nothing, and those who acquire anything do not work. The whole of this objection is but another expression of the tautology: that there can no longer be any wage-labour when there is no longer any capital.”

    I’m also reminded of the engineer, a socialist, who worked for Edison (or maybe Bell) about a hundred years ago, and attacked pretty hard the notions that profit is necessary for or even conducive to invention. Does anyone remember/know more about this? My memory is shot.

    In regard to “history is nothing but a continuous transformation of human nature”: if this is consonant with Maoism, why did Mao think that the law of value would persist for hundreds of years under socialism? (This is a genuine question I have, not a rhetorical one.)

  3. 3Nickglais said at 5:13 am on May 6th, 2009:Andrew,Thanks for your comments, and thanks for your innovative work recovering Marx’s Political Economy.I have attached a note on Mao and the Law of Value for your critical consumption.

    Mao on the Law of Value

    The law of value serves as an instrument of planning. Good. But the law of value should not be made the main basis of planning.

    We did not carry through the Great Leap on the basis of the demands of the law of value but on the basis of the fundamental economic laws of socialism and the need to expand production. If things are narrowly regarded from the point of view of the law of value the Great Leap would have to be judged not worth the losses and last year’s all-out effort to produce steel and iron as wasted labor. The local steel produced was low in quantity and quality, and the state had to make good many losses. The economic results were not significant, etc.

    The partial short-term view is that the campaign was a loss, but the overall long-term view is that there was great value to the campaign because it opened wide a whole economic construction phase. Throughout the country many new starts in steel and iron were made, and many industrial centers were built. This enabled us to step up our pace greatly.

    In the winter of 1959 over 75 million people were working on water conservancy nationwide. The method of organizing two large-scale campaigns could be used to solve our basic water conservancy problems.

    From the standpoint of one, two, or three years the value of the grain to pay for so much labor was naturally quite high. But in the longer view the campaign could considerably increase grain production and accelerate it too, and stabilize agricultural production, and so the value of commodities per unit gains. All this then goes toward satisfying the people’s need for grain. The continuing development of agriculture and light industry creates further accumulation for heavy industry.

    This too benefits people in the long run. So long as the peasants and the people of the entire country understand what the state is doing, whether money is gained or lost, they are bound to approve and not oppose. From among the peasants themselves the slogan of supporting industry has been put forward.

    There is the proof! Stalin as well as Lenin said, “In the period of socialist construction the peasantry must pay tribute to the state.” The vast majority of China’s peasants is “sending tribute” with a positive attitude. It is only among the prosperous peasants and the middle peasants, some 15 percent of the peasantry, that there is any discontent. They oppose the whole concept of the Great Leap and the people’s communes.

    In sum, we put plans ahead of prices. Of course we cannot ignore prices. A few years ago we raised the purchase price for live pigs, and this had a positive effect on pigbreeding. But for the kind of large-scale, nationwide breeding we have today, planning remains the main thing we rely on.

    Page 521 refers to the problem of pricing in the markets of collective farms. Their collective farm markets have too much freedom. It is not enough to use only state economic power to adjust prices in such markets. Leadership and control are also necessary. In our markets, during the first stage, prices were kept within certain bounds by the government. Thus small liberties were kept from becoming big ones.

    Page 522 says, “Thanks to our command of the law of value, the kind of anarchy in production or waste of social labor power the law entails under capitalism is not found in a socialist economy.”

    This makes too much of the effects of the law of value. In socialist society crises do not occur, mainly because of the ownership system: the basic laws of socialism, national planning of production and distribution, the lack of free competition or anarchy, etc., and not because we command the law of value. The economic crises of capitalism, it goes without saying, are determined by the ownership system too.

    This extract is from Mao – Critique of Soviet Economics

  4. 4Joe said at 3:44 am on May 9th, 2009:You missed the biggest difference between Marx’s labor vouchers and labor money. As Marx says in the second volume of Capital, “The producers may eventually receive paper checks, by means of which they withdraw from the social supply of means of consumption a share corresponding to their labor-time. These checks are not money. They do not circulate. “
  5. 5Andrew Kliman said at 12:06 pm on May 22nd, 2009:A reply to Nick and to Joe
    ==========================To Nick:

    Hi! Thanks for the reply. I think the key issue here is Mao’s initial premise: “The law of value serves as an instrument of planning.” Or in other words, “we command the law of value.”

    I don’t see how that can be, if one means socialist planning rather than capitalist planning. A law is something that is in control, not something one controls. The continued operation of the law of value thus implies that the direct producers are subject to economic imperatives that they cannot control and to which they must submit.

    There is a similar difference between Marx and Proudhon about this. As Seth notes in the article, Marx wrote in _The Poverty of Philosophy_ that “relative value, measured by labor time, is inevitably the formula of the present enslavement of the worker, instead of being, as M. Proudhon would have it, the ‘revolutionary theory’ of the emancipation of the proletariat.”

    To Joe:

    Okay, I’ll bite. Why is the fact that Marx’s labor vouchers don’t circulate “the biggest difference” between them and “labor money”?

    After all, there are potentially “black markets.” So there are economic relations that determine whether or not, IN FACT, the labor vouchers circulate. Thus it seems to me that the biggest differences are the differences that CAUSE the labor vouchers not to circulate.

    So I think Seth has it right when he asks, “Can we legislate the abolition of commodity production? Can politics break the law of value?” I don’t see that the non-circulation of vouchers is something that can be instituted and sustained by decree.

    Take the case that Seth presents: “what will happen when demand for a product-as with typewriters in the advent of the personal computer-drops off?” Unless there are profound changes in real economic relations that can enforce the non-circulation of the labor vouchers, what is likely to happen, I think, is

    (a) the typewriter workers don’t receive any vouchers-because their labor is not deemed necessary by “society”; or

    (b) facing imminent unemployment, they keep their jobs by “willingly” offering to accept a 1-hour voucher in exchange for a typewriter that took 2 or 3 or whatever labor-hours to produce; or

    (c) the economy breaks down because inefficiency is being rewarded and because labor and other resources are being used to produce things for which there isn’t demand, and diverted away from production of things for which there is strong demand.

  6. 6nickglais said at 11:29 am on April 10th, 2010:Here is my book on Marxism against Market Socialismhttp://democracyandclasstruggle.blogspot.com/2010/04/democracy-and-class-struggle-publishes.htmlTake a look !

    Nickglais

  7. 7bcooney said at 12:52 pm on August 19th, 2010:Andrew,I’ve read this essay multiple times but it is just now that it occurs to me to ask this. When Marx says, “and with this certificate he draws from the social stock of means of consumption as much as the same amount of labor costs.”… how do we know how many items of consumption can be withdrawn from this social stock without any measure of the average labor time it takes to make a commodity? Are you saying that commodities in the social stock are worth whatever the individual labor time went in to them, so that same commodity has a heterogeneous measure of its labor time? Or are you suggesting that centralization of production is enough that individual deviations in productivity are wiped out…. Or am I missing something crucial?

4 Comments

  1. Hi Brendan,

    In response to your comment of 12:52 pm on August 19th, 2010:

    I think Marx is saying, in the CGP, that, in the first phase of communism, an *actual* hour of labor performed will count directly as an hour of *social* labor performed. And the producer who works for an *actual* hour will be entitled to a *socially average* hour’s worth of goods and services (after deductions for the care of those who can’t work, investment, reserves for emergencies, etc.)

    Imagine that there are 100 million pairs of shoes, which altogether required 50 million labor-hours to produce. So a socially average hour of shoe-producing labor produces 100/50 = 2 pairs of shoes. (This is known as a “weighted” average. Note that no knowledge of how much labor was needed to produce each particular pair of shoes is needed to compute the weighted average.)

    A person who works for an hour would be entitled to withdraw two pairs of shoes … even if s/he worked to produce shoes but only produced 1 pair or 1/2 pair in that hour of work.

    This is what it means for labor to be directly social. Every individual hour is deemed by society to be equal to every other one (in this context).

  2. I hate to point this out, but Proudhon argued that exploitation occurred at the point of production. He did NOT explain it in terms of “unequal exchange” but rather due to wage-labour:

    http://anarchism.pageabode.com/pjproudhon/introduction.html#on-exploitation

    In fact, Proudhon’s analysis of exploitation is almost identical to Marx’s, except he stated it first:

    http://anarchism.pageabode.com/pjproudhon/proudhon-and-marx-on-exploitation

    As far as “The Poverty of Philosophy” goes, it is riddled with selective quoting, tampered quotes and things Marx just made up. It is, to a large degree, intellectually dishonest:

    http://anarchism.pageabode.com/pjproudhon/appendix-proudhon-and-marx.html#poverty

    This is not to suggest that he does not make some valid points, he does. It is to point out that much of the book paints a radically false picture of what Proudhon was arguing. I’ve footnoted the extracts from “System of Economical Contradictions” to show some examples of this:

    http://anarchism.pageabode.com/pjproudhon/system-of-economic-contradictions-1

    So, in terms of “Marx’s critique of Proudhon” it would be useful to remember that much of it is not critiquing what Proudhon actually advocated. In fact, quite the reverse as Marx repeatedly attributes ideas to Proudhon which the later explicitly opposes.

    There is a need to critique mutualism, I would agree, but Marx’s contribution is so flawed as to be misleading. I’ve made a contribution to this here:

    http://anarchism.pageabode.com/anarcho/mutualism-yes-and-no

    Clearly my forthcoming Proudhon anthology “Property is Theft!” is needed!

  3. Few words only: Proudhon broke relationships with Marx, and you know why.Yeah, that’s right:
    ” I would therefore prefer to burn Property by a slow fire, rather than give it new strength by making a St Bartholomew’s night of the proprietors …”
    Then anarchists were not welcome anymore.

  4. “Proudhon says that the contradiction between supply and demand can be overcome if commodities are made to exchange directly in proportion to the amount of labor required for their production. Set prices equal to values, so that supply and demand find equilibrium, and voila: commodities will always be exchangeable and at a fair price.”

    Where does he say that? Where does he write “set prices to equal values, so that supply and demand find equilibrium”? Marx does not quote him writing that. Indeed, Marx does not quote him advocating labour-notes.

    In fact, Proudhon explicitly states in volume 2 (the chapter on Community) that there is no need to replace money with some other institution — in volume 1, he notes that the measure for value is the Franc and does not suggest replacing it. He also indicates that he expects value to oscillate under mutualism, so he recognised that competition determines value, supply and demand.

    “Marx jokes that while everyone else ventures outside for a walk when the weather is good, Proudhon would have us leave the house to insure good weather!”

    Shame that Marx did not find the time between jokes to quote Proudhon actually advocating anything like what Marx asserts he did…

    “As a legislator, Marx tells us, Proudhon is free to decree the abolition of the law of supply and demand.”

    Where did Proudhon advocate that? Oh, right, nowhere…

    “While Proudhon was content to remain a captive of the commodity-form, there are many of us today who want to transcend commodity production and transcend capital.”

    So Proudhon wants to abolish supply and demand AND remains captive to “the commodity form”, that is buying and selling! Which shows the poverty of Marx’s “Poverty”…

    “Can we legislate the abolition of commodity production? Can politics break the law of value?”

    Which is precisely what Marx did proclaim — the replacement of the market by central planning. He was wonderfully unaware of how hard that would be — in “Poverty” he uses the example of a two person, two product economy to show its validity! Clearly someone unaware of the fallacy of composition…

    “Proudhon’s interest in the equilibration of supply and demand led him to advocate the abolition of money.”

    Where does Proudhon advocate the abolition of money? Where does he advocate labour-notes? Marx never quotes him saying this and instead invokes Bray — who was an advocate of central planning!

    “In the course of his critique of this aspect of Proudhon’s thought, Marx elaborates a crucially important notion-namely that of “directly social labor”-which is still not well understood.”

    Except, of course, Marx never shows us where Proudhon advocated this… this is unsurprising for he did not. Indeed, in volume 2 of “System of Economic Contradiction” he explicitly says that money does not need to be abolished!

    “In endeavoring an equalitarian application of Ricardo’s theory, Proudhon and left Ricardian thinkers like John Gray, advocated what we would today call monetary reform: they sought to replace money with “time chits” or “labor money.””

    Gray and Bray may have advocated “time chits” or “labor money” but Proudhon did not — that explains why Marx never quotes him advocating it and rather quotes John Bray advocating it. Bray being a central planner like Marx.

    for more discussion, see: http://anarchism.pageabode.com/anarcho/proudhon-marx-labour-notes-wage-labour

    All in all, repeating Marx’s dishonest and misleading book as if it were an accurate account of Proudhon’s ideas is part of the problem.

2 Trackbacks / Pingbacks

  1. Audio: MHI discusses state-capitalism & the nature of Soviet Union | Marxist-Humanist Initiative
  2. Audio: MHI discusses state-capitalism & the nature of Soviet Union – Marxist-Humanist Initiative

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published.


*